Book Review: War and Peace
I recently published my acx book review contest 2024 submission on Savage Money. My 2023 submission last year was a review of War and Peace. The review did not nail the notes I wanted it to1 I’m still searching for that. but it turned out good anyway. Have a hot beverage, stake out some time for a long review, and Merry Christmas!
Table of Contents
military movement is like the movement of a clock: an impetus, once given, leads inexorably to a particular result while the untouched working parts wait in silent stillness for the action to reach them. Wheels creak on their spindles as the cogs bite, the speeding sprockets hum and the next wheel stands and waits patiently, as if resigned to centuries of immobility. But the moment comes when the lever slips into place and the submissive wheel rotates with a creak, blending into the common movement without knowing where it goes or why.
In a clock the complex action of countless different wheels works its way out in the even, leisurely movement of hands measuring time; in a similar way the complex action of humanity in those 160,000 Russians and Frenchmen – all their passions, longings, regrets, humiliation and suffering, their rushes of pride, fear and enthusiasm – only worked its way out in defeat at the battle of Austerlitz, known as the battle of the three Emperors, the slow tick-tock of the age-old hands on the clock face of human history.
War and Peace is not a book about peace. Nor, really, is it a book about war. War and Peace is a book about how we think about history. Tolstoy makes an argument that humanity is more effective at shaping its past than its future: based on the contradictory-sounding observation that at any given moment we are bound by a small set of viable alternative courses of action, yet as we look back at the past, we fail to grasp the vastness of the decision space and the multitude of causes that directed the action at the time and instead, we weave logical narratives with little concern for truth.
what is so weird and ridiculous about these answers is that modern history is like a deaf man answering questions no one has asked.
Apparently War and Peace is considered one of the longest books in the world. I didn’t know that at the time, so I launched myself headfirst into what turned out to be a two-month adventure, and I made it through.
Was it worth it? After a brief pause to think, I would say “yes”.
1. Translation and Epistemology
I should preface this review by saying that I have read the Anthony Briggs translation. I don’t know a lick of Russian and only a tiny bit of French, so I can only judge the quality of the translation by the translator’s notes in the beginning of the book. It sounds to me like Briggs has done an excellent and well-researched job. In this review, I will speak of the author as “Tolstoy”, but obviously I can’t speak for anything but “Briggs”.
Of relevance is also my knowledge about this period of history in general, and the Napoleonic campaigns specifically: I didn’t know much before I started reading War and Peace. It piqued my interest to the point where I have read other sources on the period (e.g. The Fox of the North by Parkinson), but in general, my knowledge should be considered limited to that which is described by Tolstoy. Our collective understanding of things may well have evolved since, which would make some of the historical remarks in this review outdated.
2. Themes
War and Peace is three things:
- a novel about some people in early 19th century Russia;
- an historical accounting of critical events during the Napoleonic wars between 1805 and 1813; and
- most important of all, a treatise on causality, chance, authority, and cognitive biases.
It seems to me Tolstoy was unhappy with the disconnect between history as it is told and reality as it is experienced. For an example, take this very moment, as it plays out across the world in an instant. Think especially of the trends in movements of people, both near to you, and in countries far from you. The moment is now part of history, much like the kings or revolutions or emigrations from the books, but it doesn’t feel like it, because when we write history down after the fact, it comes out different to how it was at the time. Written history tends to flow according to some logical progression, in a way the moment-to-moment experience of our lives do not. When we speak of the past, we assume there is some sort of cohesive plan according to which people do things, with one thing being a clear consequence of another, whereas in the moment, we experience a bombardment of opinions, random events, and desires that pull us in so many directions it’s surprising we get anything done at all.
Tolstoy is in good company. These observations have been made more recently by e.g. statisticians (de Finetti in Theory of Probability) and systems safety analysts (Leveson in Engineering a Safer World), to name just two examples. In systems safety, we see accident reports that say things like “the operator inserted the probe in the secondary channel, which caused a backflow of chemicals, and that led to spontaneous combustion. If the operator had inserted the probe in the primary channel as per instructions, this wouldn’t have been a problem.” True as that might be, is it the interesting bit? Shouldn’t we at least try to figure out why the operator thought insertion into the secondary channel was a good idea at the time? And is probe insertion into the secondary channel a guarantee for backflow? Is there nothing else that causes backflow? Why was the system designed to allow unsafe backflow in the first place? These are questions a systems safety analyst has to ask, because most people won’t. Most people will accept the idea that the operator should have done things one way and through some fault of character, perhaps, decided to do things another way.
Or, as the problem is reflected in the book: “Why did 600,000 men collectively decide to walk from France to Russia, eat all the food there was to be had along the way, only to starve and freeze to death on the way home?”
They should have not done that.
Historians in Tolstoy’s time had an answer: they did it because their Emperor, Napoleon, ordered them to. Or because great men had written books that created a political climate in which it was the right thing to do. Tolstoy thinks these are insufficient explanations, although the latter certainly seem closer to the truth than the former. But we are getting ahead of ourselves.
3. Aristocratic Life and Chance
while their elders began talking about Bonaparte, Julie, Madame Karagin’s daughter, turned to young Rostov, and said, ’I missed you at the Arkharovs on Thursday. It was very dull without you,’ she said, giving him a sweet smile. Feeling flattered, he flashed a flirtatious young man’s smile and moved closer to her. They started a private conversation, blissfully unaware that his spontaneous smile had pierced a jealous Sonya to the heart; she was left with a forced expression of pretended enjoyment on her blushing face.
War and Peace opens up with highly detailed glimpses into the lives of Russian aristocrats in the early 19th century. I didn’t know anything about aristocratic life in early 19th century Russia (or anywhere else, at any other time, for that matter) before reading this book. I have since gathered from other sources that these people were fairly disconnected from reality, in the “let them eat cake” sense. Tolstoy doesn’t go into that. Himself being an aristocrat in 19th century Russia, he looks at the other aristocrats as fellow humans. With unique and sometimes strange personalities, yes, but otherwise much like you and me.
If you have read a novel about humans before, you won’t find anything earth-shattering about this theme in War and Peace.
There are two reasons these glimpses matter: first, we get to know the protagonists through whose eyes we suffer the madness of humanity. More importantly, they provide a civilian perspective on an eventful decade of history. Tolstoy did a lot of research, including talking to people who lived through these years. He shares with us what it looked like to people at the time, as it happened. Unsurprisingly, a lot of people had more important matters in their lives than some war a French emperor dragged their army into: love, finances, reputation, work, religion, to name a few. Put simply, life at the time didn’t totally circle around the wars, in contrast to the historic recollections. War and other grand gestures of violence leave very obvious scars for historians to study, which means it occupies a lot of space in the literature. But humans then were very much like humans now, and they had real lives outside of what ended up in history books.
The wars were, of course, on people’s lips. You gossiped about them for signaling value, e.g. to show that you are politically well connected, and you know Count so-and-so whose nephew was in the front with Prince Fancy Pants. But people weren’t concerned about the war – until they were. But it happened first gradually, then suddenly. As with any big change, it took people by surprise, no matter how obvious it seems in hindsight. Why do big changes happen that way? We’ll get to that.
One of the common threads throughout the book is the – actual and perceived – influence of chance on outcomes.
the officer grinned through his whiskers at the orderly’s tone, dismounted, gave his horse to a servant, and walked over to Bolkonsky with a slight bow. Bolkonsky made room for him on the bench. The hussar sat down beside him. […]
’Oh, you must be Prince Bolkonsky! Delighted to meet you. Lieutenant–Colonel Denisov, better known as Vaska,’ said Denisov, shaking hands with Prince Andrey and looking him in the face with warm friendliness. […] Prince Andrey knew about Denisov from Natasha’s stories of when she was first wooed. The bitter-sweet memory brought back the heart ache he hadn’t even thought about in recent days, though it still lay buried in his soul.
For example, people the reader has been acquainted with just happen to stumble over each other in odd situations. At first glance this struck me as unrealistic – I even stopped suspending my disbelief at one point – but then I realised it’s all an effect of selection. There were in the order of thousands of hypothetical aristocrats the book could have been about, but Tolstoy focuses from the beginning on the specific combination of people that happen to encounter each other by chance later, because that makes for a more interesting novel. It also happens to foreshadow Tolstoy’s idea of causality.
Once chance has had us end up in a situation, as much as we feel free, we often find that we have limited ability to get ourselves into a different situation. For all the talk about free will, in any given moment, we are bound to a small set of reasonable alternatives. Sometimes due to physical laws, sometimes biological necessities, and sometimes social expectations.
kutuzov woke up, cleared his throat hoarsely and scanned the generals. ’Gentlemen,’ he said, ’the disposition for tomorrow, no, for today – it’s past midnight – cannot now be changed. You have heard it, and we shall all do our duty.’
This is straight out of the history books; the real-life Kutuzov made this remark, after a long lecture by the war theorist Weyrother about how the Russo-Austrian alliance were sure to win the battle of Austerlitz (which they subsequently lost). Kutuzov had been of the firm opinion that the battle of Austerlitz was lost even before it was fought, and the plan presented by Weyrother would make things worse. For political reasons, Kutuzov did not have the ability to question the plan on short notice; his previous strategic retreats had gotten him a reputation as a person who is too intimidated by violence to go to battle, and any objection to this plan would be seen as confirming evidence of that reputation, rather than taken as a serious concern.
By the time the plan was presented, Kutuzov had two reasonable choices: submit to the plan as written, or resign in protest. Kutuzov chose to submit to the plan, because as much as he didn’t believe in it, he felt duty-bound to the soldiers he commanded and his country, and wanted an opportunity to make the execution slightly less catastrophic than the plan indicated.
For a further lesson in how chance affects things, Tsar Alexander himself happened to pass by Kutuzov’s units as they were holding back, and the Tsar assumed command over Kutuzov’s units, sending them into the lost battle.
5. Historical Causality
Tolstoy focuses on what we might call anthropocentric causality, in that he looks specifically at humans causing behaviour in other humans. This might seem like a narrow view, but it is a logical starting point. Even if our interest in causality is limited to an apparently self-contained model like a block on an inclined plane – someone (a human!) must have put the block there in response to something done by someone else (another human!). In that case, the other human is the one causing the behaviour in the first. Even if we believe that humans can be an ultimate cause, i.e. do things entirely uninfluenced by anything else, we may agree that most of what humans do, especially in joint efforts, depends on the opinions of other people.
As in the case of the sergeant and Auersperg at the Tabor bridge, what we are concerned about, even more specifically, is not the power stemming from logical reasoning or physical inevitability (we can simply take that for granted), but the more fickle and common kind, our ability to influence the actions of humans beyond what’s in our direct control. We will also speak as if we are discussing people giving direct orders to other people, because that is a case that usually leaves fairly obvious traces in history, but the same reasoning applies also to more subtle forms of influencing other people’s behaviour.
5.1 What Power is Not
it would all be very fascinating if we still recognised a divine power, self-sustaining and immutable, guiding nations through the agency of your Napoleons, Louis, and writers, but we no longer acknowledge any such power, and so, before we can start talking about Napoleons, Louis, and great writers, we have to demonstrate some kind of connection between those persons and the movements of nations. If some other power is substituted for divine will, we have to explain what it consists of, since this power is the very focus of all historical interest.
If we believe in God, history looks simple: God commanded the leaders of humanity (be they monarchs, generals, writers, or administrators) to issue orders, and God made sure the people followed those orders. If we dare leave that explanation behind, it gets trickier. When it comes to the influential autocrats of the past, one sometimes sees arguments that they did have godlike powers of command due to personality traits; that they are exceptionally clever, or charismatic, or duplicitous, and this is why people couldn’t resist following their orders. This is not even nearly a complete explanation because a lot of people share those traits without wielding exceptional power, and even the leaders that do possess these personality traits occasionally gain and lose their power throughout their lives, with their general personality being fairly constant.
It is clear to most that barring intervention by God, individuals simply don’t have the social standing to actually directly issue arbitrary orders to (and be obeyed by!) hundreds of people – maybe not even tens of people. One way to attempt to sidestep the issue of individual power is to say that the leaders of humanity weren’t able to do all the things we ascribe to them. Rather, it was their aides, advisors, and other high-ranking officials who wore the actual power of command. It should be clear, though, that this stops analysis short of its target. We still need a concept like individual power to explain how the orders of a high-ranking official were carried out by the masses. (Tolstoy likens it to trying to explain the movement of an object through component forces that don’t add up to the total acceleration.)
We could take the same idea further, though, and claim that movements of people are not driven by people, but by intellectual ideas, or religion, or scarcity of resources, or some other pet explanation. But as long as we focus on a single type of cause only, we will run into contradictions where we need to explain opposite effects using the same cause. Christianity made Jesus turn the other cheek and conquistadors kill indigenous Americans. Scarcity made Norwegians issue egalitarian rations and Hondurans concentrate wealth to a few people.
If we try to remain flexible by appealing to the most relevant concern for any given event, claiming that “The Iraq war was about politics, and Boko Haram is about religion” and so on, then we run into trouble when trying to specify, ahead of time, which driving force will be relevant at any given time. If that is only apparent once something has happened, it is wild speculation, not theoretical fact.
The problem in any of these attempts to explain the causes of events is that by focusing on specific people, specific countries, specific ideas, specific politics, specific religions, specific practices, etc. comes a myopic view of history. With the myopic view, we have to deal with the disconnect between the thing we are looking at, and the much greater picture: the movements of people. The movements of people have never followed a specific, single thing to any great extent. To bridge this gap, we are forced to invent an abstraction. Power is the word we use to account for the difference between the thing we are studying and what actually happens, and this explains why power behaves so mysteriously: it’s the negative of a mechanism, it’s what accounts for everything we have not been able to derive logically. Power, in this abstract sense, might seem real, it may even help explain a few things, but in the end it’s a model with limited applicability, to paraphrase de Finetti on phlogiston.
One way to embrace this idea of power as an abstraction is to say that the leaders of humanity have power because they act according to the collective will of the people. There are different variants of this argument, but all of them run into inconsistencies around edge cases, leaving important mechanisms unexplained. Does all behaviour of a leader reflect the will of the people? Is transfer of power unconditional? Can it be shared by multiple people? This model is particularly shifty because in its most general shape, it can explain everything – and thus nothing. With hindsight, we can always point to a person and say that they had power because the people willed it, but the mechanics for how the will of the people shifts between leaders is never elucidated. It is like pointing to the sheep at the head of the flock and saying that “they all follow that sheep”. Well, until the sheep collectively change direction and appear to follow another sheep that happened to be at the front at that instant.
When we could say “God made them do it” power was not an abstraction. God was the ultimate cause of all events. But now we are looking for a different explanation. We are forced to treat “power” as a non-explanatory abstraction. If we lift the veil of “power”, what mechanism will we find underneath?
5.2 Direct Effect of Orders
our false impression that an order preceding an event is the cause of it is due to the fact that when an event has occurred and one or two orders out of a thousand issued have been carried out (the ones that happen to engage with the course of events), we forget those that were not carried out because they never could have been.
First of all, as we observe throughout the book as well as in our own experiences, orders do not categorically lead to action, and in particular, not the specific action dictated by the order. Orders are neither necessary nor sufficient for carrying out an action: we know that Napoleon issued a lot of orders, with only a tiny fraction carried out precisely according to his will. Similarly, most of what happened in the Grande Armée happened without a corresponding order from Napoleon.
It does happen that people follow orders. The correlation is clearly not zero. An order provides a weak push in the direction of an action, but for that push to result in anything, the person receiving the order must already be sufficiently predisposed to the action. We could say that the predisposition is much more the real cause behind the action, but that’s a little unfair, because the predisposition is, of course, not a single thing. The predisposition is built up from thousands of experiences, big and small, internal and external, that have affected a person over their lifetime. This is what makes the cause of an action so inscrutable. We generally cannot point to one thing and say “that was it!” It may seem like we can (“Napoleon said march onwards and they marched onwards!”) but this would ignore all the times similar orders did not have the same effect, or all the times similar outcomes happened despite different orders being issued.
We are, in other words, forced to grapple with the complication that multiple people in the same situation generally have similar ideas on what the best course of action is, and even if an order appears to be followed, it may just be that the people apparently following the order had similar ideas on what to do. The fact that people generally don’t follow orders to the letter, but rather some variant of it (that they think are a slight improvement), could be taken as an indication of this.
We also have to take into account feedback effects. The people giving orders are part of the effort of accomplishing something, and as such, the orders they issue are influenced by the opinions of the people who are going to receive the order, and the way orders pan out (or don’t) affects the way the next order is formed.
These considerations imply that we cannot reason about the direct effects of orders as if things followed a simple logical connection from order to action, because orders are a part of the system of actions, and the relationship between the order and the action is both complicated and weak.
5.3 Aggregation of Outcomes
our major source of error arises from the fact that in any historical account a whole series of innumerable, disparate and trivial events (say every single thing responsible for bringing the French soldiers over to Russia) are subsumed into the single end-result of that series of events, and the whole series of orders issued are correspondingly subsumed into a single expression of will.
Further confounding the study of causation is the fact that we tend to speak of the outcome as predetermined from the situation where we start observation. Yesterday I walked to a café and got a sandwich there. It is tempting to say that the purpose of my walk was to feed myself, but the truth is I actually just wanted to take out the garbage. Once outside I realised the weather was nice, and I had a doctor’s appointment an hour later that I might as well walk to. On the way there, I got a call from the doctor’s office letting me know that the doctor had gotten sick and needed to reschedule my appointment, I decided to walk home a slightly different route for variation, and noticed a drop in energy levels which I attributed to the long time that had passed since I last ate. A few minutes later I passed by the café and figured I might try a sandwich to see if my energy levels recover. The fact that I fed myself was at least the sixth coincidence during that walk – and this is not counting more mundane coincidences like the fact that I’m well-off enough that I can afford spontaneously buying an expensive sandwich and live in a location where I can walk to my doctor.
This is, perhaps, an unusual example, but this constantly plays out at smaller and larger scales through our lives. We make tiny decisions this way and that way, and before we know it, they have all aggregated together into an outcome that we didn’t predict, nor intend to achieve. If we’re lucky, we did intend to achieve something similar to it, but rarely exactly the very thing that happened.
This is one of the reasons things seem to happen first gradually, then suddenly. When we look back at where we arrived, we can see all the little causes leading up to it, but in the thick of things, those very same causes do not point reliably in one specific direction. If a drunk man goes out of the bar, turns in the direction of his home, and then every second he randomly staggers either forward or back, he cannot tell whether he will end up closer to or further away from his home, but we know for sure that he will end up further and further away from the bar as time goes on. At some point, he will look towards the bar and say, “How did I end up here?” It all happened gradually, one random step at a time, some of them away from home and some of them towards home. But as he looks back, he will feel that he ended up where he is rather suddenly, because there was no strong force that directed him that way. It was all random chance.
5.4 The Nature of Power
when an event takes place various opinions and desires are expressed about it, and as the event evolves out of the concerted action of many men, one particular version of the opinions or desires expressed is bound to be fulfilled, if only approximately. When one of the opinions expressed is fulfilled, that opinion becomes enshrined, by association, as the order that preceded the event.
Going back to the analogy of the drunk man stumbling forward and back randomly: maybe his friends have him under watch, and they are placing wagers on whether he’ll end up closer to or further from home after an hour has passed. Some will bet he ends up closer to home, and some further away. But he will end up somewhere – let’s say it’s further from home. The people who wagered on this outcome might exclaim, “I knew it! Give me my five bucks.”
“I knew it!” is a funny phrase to use in this context; the drunk man (at least in this thought experiment) goes forward or back entirely randomly each second, so nobody could have known where he would end up. But if someone does claim after the fact that they knew it, and they even present the wager as evidence, should we accept their clairvoyance? No, clearly not. They were just lucky. There’s no way to prove that they were lucky (they can always claim they were clairvoyant in this specific situation only, and the situation has passed so we cannot run the experiment again), but we know it intuitively, and through Occam’s razor (which is what makes the razor such a valuable tool).
Yet the same thing happens all the time when people issue orders and they appear to be obeyed. Not only does the outcome rarely match the order exactly, but we also have to ask ourselves, is it possible that if the course of events ran in another direction, someone else could claim to have issued the order to do that? Upon closer examination, we often find that among the multitude of orders issued, or opinions proclaimed, there will be at least one matching any plausible course of events. In other words, the order that did happen to match the outcome played a fairly small role in the outcome itself, which was a statistical accident based on the predisposition of the situation.
In my professional life, I recently witnessed a political struggle between a high-level manager (Bob) and their direct report (Alice), where Alice ended up getting promoted over Bob. What was the struggle about? Bob was leading a very large project that Alice thought was wasteful and a big risk to the organisation. The official reason for the promotion was that Alice was right and Bob was wrong – if you would ask anyone in the organisation, they would say the same thing: obviously Alice’s plan is much better. In reality, there were no objective measurements taken. Even in the same situation, had the organisation gone with Bob’s plan instead, I’m confident Bob would have looked like a genius and Alice would have been passed over for the next promotion. Note what the difference between the two scenarios is! It’s which plan happened to be followed, and it has nothing to do with the quality of the plan.
In general, people in business who are in a position to issue orders have ended up in that position by being lucky in (or good at!) having opinions that seem to match the outcome. This is amplified in most businesses because they tend to measure success by “percent of plan completed” so someone who has had the hindsight-correct opinion many times will look very successful, because large portions of their plan is completed – or rather, large portions of what is completed happened to be in their plan. Don’t mistake this for malice! The lottery winner is not at fault for causing everyone else to lose.
history shows that these forms of justifications are no less nonsensical and contradictory than, for instance, murdering someone as a declaration of his human rights, or murdering millions in Russia to take England down a peg or two. But these justifications are very necessary at the time, shifting moral responsibility away from the men who produce the events. These short-term measures operate like brushes on the front of a train clearing the rails ahead: they sweep away men’s moral responsibility.
It might seem odd that we allow some people to not participate very actively in the work itself, but rather have opinions about it. A ceo, for example, is generally the least informed person in the room when it comes to anything, yet it is essentially their job description to sit around and have opinions on how the work is performed.
Tolstoy argues the function of these opinion-havers is to provide justification for the work, to prevent the workers from having to consider why they are really doing something. This is extremely apparent when it comes to war (why am I killing my fellow humans, who have not personally affronted me or my family in any way?) but it is also relevant in today’s bureaucratised society (why am I really filling in these tps reports, when they don’t improve the lives of anyone but just make things more complicated and take longer?)
As a side effect, people whose job it is to sit around and have opinions are rather likely to have a lot of opinions, and thus many of the things that happen will – by chance – coincide with some of their opinions, and they will seem successful for giving the order that caused what happened to happen.
5.5 Determinism
At the end, Tolstoy starts making a really ambitious argument: he takes a fairly basic (though very wordy) stance in favour of determinism. In this, I feel, Tolstoy makes a leap from actual science into metaphysics, and since I’m not much of a philosopher, I don’t care much for that argument.
The reason Tolstoy goes there, though, is interesting. It’s not to philosophise for its own sake. Tolstoy has a more important mission than that: he looks around him and sees the frightening pace at which natural sciences are able to generalise laws of physics, chemistry, and biology. Given enough information about an object, we can consult e.g. Hamiltonian mechanics to determine its precise past and future. The events of a closed mechanical (or chemical, or …) system are time-invariant: there is no ultimate cause of any event, because they all depend on each other according to precise laws.
Tolstoy reasons that under the hypothesis of determinism, the same must be true for all human activity.
We used to think orders (the changing wills of leaders of humanity) caused events, and this would have been difficult to derive laws from. As we have seen, it could well be the other way around: orders follow events, through a survivor effect and/or selection bias. Given that, we can ignore the changing wills of people, and maybe there is a set of laws that would precisely describe human activity.
The mission Tolstoy sets out for historians, then, is not weaving neat stories about what must have happened in the past. It’s finding out exactly what those hard laws of human behaviour must be. We have a vast pile of historic human behaviour that we are adding by the minute. Surely, if there exists a set of laws that would let us perfectly predict human behaviour, we must be able to figure it out with the data we have at our disposal, even if we’re not strictly able to run experiments (because how could we, under the assumption of determinism?)
I think this is a great perspective on what history could be. And maybe it is necessary to rest it on a hypothesis of determinism, but I’m not convinced of that part. I think we can find statistical generalities without going into metaphysics. (And I suppose, to some extent, this is what economists and actuaries do, not historians.)
6. Conclusion
This review, despite its length, just scratches the surface of War and Peace. I realised when re-reading portions of it for this review that it’s the kind of work that seems to expand and deepen when you go back to it. However, I have to wrap the review up somewhere, and this is as good a place as any.
We started with a question that we are now ready to answer with more sophistication: why did 600,000 men collectively decide to walk from France to Russia, eat all the food there was to be had along the way, only to starve and freeze to death on the way home?
The short answer is they did not. Elaborating on that, each person decided, for their own personal and diverse reasons, to join the army. Then each person decided to march toward Russia for one more day. Circumstances and chance resulted in this happening a large number of days, for a large number of people. The same people, due to their shared situation, happened to lose this desire to walk in Russia around the same time, and turned around toward what they felt was the safest road home. They had other concerns they thought more important than the fact that along that road, they had already consumed everything the landscape had to offer on their way in.
Nobody in particular made it this way. It was just one of the many possible courses of action that happened to materialise. Some high-ranking officials condoned this activity, and helped provide justification for it, and thus it seems like they ordered it.
Like any other outcome, this specific outcome was incredibly unlikely before it materialised. Once it did, it became part of our frame of reference and it’s hard to imagine the same causes leading to some other course of action – but maybe they might have. This is the mission Tolstoy sets out to historians: what are the laws that would allow us to tell?